Altogether we can (minimally) characterise each emotion in terms of three factors: i) whether the underlying valent representation is positive or negative; ii) the nature of the contrast structure involved (temporal, modal, or social); and iii) the specific kind of response triggered (e.g., running away versus retching), which helps to specify the type of object.
COPING POTENTIAL
A crucial difference between my theory and somaticist theories (such as Deonna and Teroni 2012; Hufendiek 2016) is that while I think bodily responses play a necessary role in emotions, I do not think the feelings of those changes are necessary for emotions. In particular, it is possible to have an emotion where one is unconscious of one’s bodily changes. However, I think bodily feelings play a supplementary role in capturing a distinct, though complementary, sort of intentional content which I call emotional bodily feeling (also refer to my 2017 paper, which is an earlier version of chapter four of my book[5]).
While emotional bodily feelings are not necessary for emotions in general, they are necessary for some emotions, because they add an additional layer of control. The sophistication here is that by tracking one’s automatically triggered bodily responses and anticipating how well this bodily response can manage one’s situation, one can then stimulate further responses that modulate or inhibit one’s initial reaction. This is analogous to what psychologists like Klaus Scherer (2005) call “coping potential.”
In order to grasp the important role that this extra control level has, let us analyse the emotion of sadness. On my view, sadness requires at least three control layers:
First layer: we have an underlying concern. This can be either a positively valent attraction to something (e.g., your beloved), or a negatively valent aversion to something (e.g., being hit). Basic attractions and aversions do not require contrast representations. When the level of the attractant is low, a response is simply triggered to increase the level.
Second layer: we represent the attractant as lost (this is a temporal contrast) or an avoidant as gained. This representation automatically triggers a response to reduce the presence of the loss (so it’s a negatively valent representation in that sense) by restoring the presence of the lost thing.
Third layer: so far, this response is common to both anger and sadness, so we need a third layer to differentiate anger from sadness. The third layer is where the initial bodily response is represented, but then appraised as inadequate to restore the loss. This leads to a secondary response to inhibit the first set of responses, and to engage compensatory responses instead. That is, sadness is overall the valent representation of being unable to restore a loss.
Meanwhile, anger is where you do feel powerful enough to meet the challenge, and you gear yourself precisely to do this, to get back the lost thing, or to remove the barriers to getting it. However, anger can burn itself out if, by trying, you find you can do absolutely nothing about it, in which case I would expect the response to switch to sadness.
I would also allow the following qualification to the above causal model for sadness. It seems possible that instead of fully triggering the initial restoration response, we simply prepare this response at a neural level. This may be sufficient to generate a bodily feeling, in line with what Antonio Damasio (2000) calls the “as-if loop” of bodily feeling. It should also be sufficient to enable the individual’s coping potential to be calculated, and the response accordingly modulated, prior to triggering useless restoration responses. However, I still claim that it is
[page 8]
typical of sadness that an initial restorative response is triggered. For example, in the film Brokeback Mountain, there’s a very moving scene at the end where Ennis embraces the shirt of his dead lover Jack. Ennis wants Jack, so he grasps at this token, but he’s also keenly aware that he cannot get Jack back, and that is the core of his desperate sadness.
A secondary, but I think significant consequence of this theory of coping potential is that it allows for an additional form of value on top of the experience of pleasure. Basically, when one anticipates or judges that one’s responses are sufficient to deal with potential demands, one feels confident or powerful. Achieving this feeling can be an important source of motivation.
SOCIAL EMOTIONS
So far we have four control levels: valent representation, affect, contrast representations, and coping potential. To make sense of the social emotions we need even more. Often, when we think of social emotions we are thinking of particular emotions like jealousy, contempt, or gratitude. However, we should regard social emotionality as an additional layer of regulation that sits on top of regular emotional states. On this view, most human emotions have a social aspect.
To explain this, I once again appeal to control theory. I claim that social emotions are a valent representation aimed at regulating a relationship. In particular, social emotions involve the regulation of what I call a group’s “affiliative status.” The affiliative status between two or more people is defined as a combination of their power relationship and their intimacy relationship. Our intimacy relationship is fixed by the range of things we are disposed to cooperate on (e.g., from bodily pleasures to paying the bills). Our power relationship characterises what we can expect from each other in terms of support (I might serve you more than you serve me). Thus, I may have a relatively intimate and equal relationship with my wife, while I have a relatively distant and power-unbalanced relationship with my boss.
A group’s affiliative status can change over time, but crucially, members form expectations about how other members are supposed to act in conformity with it. This includes both the way we treat each other, and the attitudes we might expect ourselves to share towards events in the shared environment (e.g., finding the same things amusing, disgusting or annoying). Thus, if my wife behaves in a way contrary to this expectation, I will respond emotionally in a way aimed at restoring the expected relationship. My wife may equally think that my behaviour fails to cohere with our affiliative status. Thus, she may respond emotionally in kind. In this way a social-emotional negotiation will take place, and hopefully we will eventually end up on the same page, emotionally speaking. If not, this will probably lead to a change in our affiliative relationship.
The principle mechanism by which social emotions function is via expressions in the face, voice, and posture. I largely follow Mitchell Green (2007) in thinking that expressions signal to each other our emotional states for the sake of social negotiation (cf. behavioural ecology views). I supplement this with my analysis of emotional bodily feelings, that is, the experience we have of the bodily changes triggered in emotional states. Both when I trigger the various bodily changes associated with anger, and when I observe someone else doing the same thing, the same mechanism is involved in taking that pattern of responses to represent the capability and disposition of the agent to act in a certain way. For anger, in particular, a reciprocal pattern of expressions allows agents to compare their relative preparedness to attack, and negotiate and establish their affiliative status without resorting to physical violence.
A crucial part of my account is that an affiliative status does not belong to the individual. No individual can unilaterally establish a settled relationship with anyone else. It has to be agreed by all parties involved. As a result,
[page 9]
I argue that the regulative process must be understood as a collective phenomenon. I resist calling this social level of regulation a collective emotion, contra Margaret Gilbert (2000). I think we can do everything we need with the notion of social norms. These norms only exist at the social level, and thus there is something irreducibly collective going on. But we need not suppose the existence of group minds or group mental states. These social norms can moreover spread through a population, allowing for the development of cultural-emotional patterns.
In retrospect, I should have made more explicit connections in my book to the reactive attitude tradition in ethics, i.e., the idea we get from Peter Strawson that moral relationships are often a matter of feeling and expressing certain emotional states. I talk about social emotionality in larger groups in the book, but I only briefly mention the moral community. Note in particular that when the group is larger than a dyad, you can have an emotion aimed at regulating the affiliative status of the group where one group member has harmed another group member, though you are not affected. In this way, my model of social emotions can apply to the resentment or sympathy we might feel for persons we have little contact with, but who are still members of our moral community.
REASON AND EMOTION
Reason and emotion are often supposed to be at odds with each other. From one perspective, our emotions are like unruly toddlers–demanding and whimsical–that need to be held in check by the adult intellect. From another perspective, the rational mind is cold and calculating, and needs the warmth of the passions to grasp what really matters. I don’t think that either of these perspectives, properly understood, is wrong. Where they are potentially confusing is if they suggest that emotions and reason are two separate sources of agency vying for supremacy. For instance, Plato encourages this confusion with his tripartite model of the soul (e.g., in The Republic, Cooper and Hutchinson eds. 1997). Kant does the same in the Critique of Practical Judgement ([1788] 2002, bk. 1, ch. 3) when he supposes that the rational grasp of moral imperatives can motivate action independently, and even in rejection of our passionate impulses.
In contrast to Plato and Kant, we must remember that humans (and other animals) are single agents, and we have not evolved the resources of emotion and reason to fight against each other, but to ever more effectively protect the things we care about. Given this consideration, I think the correct thing to say is that reason elaborates emotion. That is, it’s yet another layer of control.
Most philosophers and psychologists of emotion agree that emotions have a descriptive function (alongside their motivational function). Emotions inform us about the state of the world; that it is dangerous, enviable, disgusting, and so on. Naturally, the kinds of properties we are describing rely on the person caring about certain things; they are relative to the individual in this sense. But given that the person cares about certain things (e.g., the integrity of his body, the status of his loved ones) it can be entirely factual that a situation threatens or supports him. Now along comes the capacity for rational inference. This allows the emotions to massively expand their capacity to track the things the individual cares about, to check whether the initial emotional representation is accurate, to infer consequences, and have further emotions towards those consequences. This, I contend, is the main purpose of reason.
At the same time, it is misleading to say that reason is slave to the passions, as David Hume ([1739] 1978) famously declares in A Treatise of Human Nature. I claim that the motivational juice driving all cognition is drawn from our underlying homeostatic regulation systems. Emotions are one cognitive resource for elaborating these systems, while rational inferences are a further resource. This means that one concern-regulating system can overrule another, where the first is rationally elaborated and the second is not.
[page 10]
The resulting experience can be one where we rationally infer that acting impulsively (say to run away from giving an important speech) could destroy one’s reputation, and we accordingly stop ourselves. Thus, there is room for motivational conflict, but nothing so simple as reason controlling emotion. We could as easily say that one emotion is controlling another emotion here, or that one kind of thinking is controlling another kind of thinking.
CHARACTER
One final layer of control is required before we have a reasonably complete picture of our emotional lives. This is character. I analyse character as the combination of an individual’s sentiments. Sentiments are basically long-term attitudes that we bear towards specific individuals, institutions, or causes; that is, the things that we love or hate. The important difference that such sentiments make is in getting an individual to prioritise the regulation of certain concerns over others, in ways that can allow other emotional processes to be overruled. For example, when I love my children, I prioritise their flourishing over most other concerns. For instance, I may act to protect them even when it compromises my own safety. So, the fear for my safety can be overruled by the concern for my children.
The most distinctive cognitive feature of sentiments is that they require us to track unique individuals, not just general types of aversive or attractive situations. Tracking unique individuals is, I argue, our most sophisticated representational activity. In particular, it necessitates that we generate a narrative history about the individual. These narrative histories pick out individuals so uniquely that they could not be replaced by another individual with the same set of qualities. The replacements lack the same history.
Once we understand the way that love uniquely tracks individuals, we can make sense of long-term affective phenomena like grief. Peter Goldie (2012) uses the example of grief to defend his narrative model of emotions because he thinks there is no essential emotional response or representation (instead we have different stages of grief that we link together). However, I argue that we can treat grief as a control process in fundamentally the same manner as other emotions. The key complication of grief over sadness is that the underlying concern attaches to a unique individual. Because the attachment is to a unique individual, this makes it impossible for the usual response to either restore or compensate the loss. Thus, a slow process is required where the control system has to gradually learn to no longer seek the presence of the loved one. The changes in strategy will correspond to the different stages of grief.
Finally, note that character is not the same as personality. I provide a characterisation of personality in the book in terms of general strategies that individuals develop to regulate their concerns. These strategies standardly combine the sensitivity to a certain concern, (e.g., one’s social relationships), with capacities, (e.g., one’s capacity to empathise with others). Like character, personality serves to individuate people since some people are more sensitive and more capable of regulating certain values than others. Moreover, personality traits are typically stable over the long term. However personality operates at all levels of regulation, so it is not a distinct layer of control in the same way as character.
A CONTROL THEORY OF THE MIND
The final chapter of my book is on mental architecture. This is where I propose a control theory of the mind as a whole. It is perhaps the most ambitious and speculative chapter of a book that is probably already too ambitious for its own good. I am trying to fit together all the various mental processes that I have analysed up to that point (homeostatic processes, pains and pleasures, emotions, bodily feelings, social emotions, emotion-driven thinking, and character traits).
[page 11]
At the foundations of the mental architecture I propose lie the valent representations; basic negative feedback control mechanisms that track simple properties and automatically trigger regulative responses. As we evolve more sophisticated ways to represent information, new types of affective state emerge. The basic idea is that new kinds of state elaborate the fundamental control structure, each new level building incrementally upon the last. Thus, representational sophistications develop for the sake of guiding our regulative processes more effectively. The more purely descriptive cognitive and perceptual functions are by-products of these developments.
In more detail, I outline the specific levels in the development of mental architecture, corresponding to the different affective states I analyse over the course of the book. Here is where the theory is most tentative, but it follows a general logic of how complexity develops step by step. That is, we need cognition of a certain complexity to be in place before cognition of a slightly greater complexity can plausibly emerge.
Key to the development of cognitive complexity, in my view, is the interaction and competition between multiple valent representations. First they inhibit each other. That is, the triggering of one valent representation prevents another valent representation from launching a conflicting response. Then valent representations start to associatively support each other, probably because some properties or the responses they trigger are more mutually compatible than others. Mutually supporting systems are motivated by the need to overcome the inhibitions of competing systems.
The next step in complexity is the formation of higher-level representations. Higher-level representations infer structures or objects behind first-order appearances (cf. connectionist approaches). They go beyond the mere bundles of properties that association captures. I claim that the model of affect I outlined, in which failure and success of regulation is represented, is the first higher-order representation. It is higher-order because it represents objects and the individual’s own responses as bearing a relationship with each other. This is not a simple appearance. As mentioned above, affect also plays a special role in assigning attention, thus again serving the competition between valent representational systems.
Emotions then involve a further sophistication, since they involve not just a representation of states of affairs, but a comparison between the current state of affairs and some other state (e.g., in the past or future). Emotional bodily feelings and our awareness of the emotions of others via their expressive behaviour are the next step, involving a simulation of how an agent may behave in the future. This allows new kinds of calculations to be performed where the individual contrasts their emotional state with the emotions of others or represents them as coordinated in some respect, as in social emotional regulation.
The next steps involve the development of symbolic reference and inference rules. This is of course a major development of mind, and even in the book I can only roughly sketch how it fits into the architecture. A basic idea is that once we have social-emotional norms, we are coordinating our references to the world, and we thereby have the beginnings of shared symbolic references to the world. For example, the shared expression of disgust comes to symbolically reference the disgusting object. However, when it comes to mental architecture, I think a whole new series of developments in representational sophistication build upon the basic foundation of symbolic thinking. I entertain the possibility that the developments in complexity in our symbolic/inferential capacities parallel the prior development of complexity in affective states.
Finally, as described in the previous section, the capacity to generate narrative histories allows us to track unique individuals and to prioritise their well-being over more general or short-term situations. The full table of steps is provided below (figure 5).
[page 12]